Tuesday, October 31, 2017

Can a macro model be good for policy, but not for forecasting?

During the course of an ongoing debate with Britonomist sparked by my earlier post, he argued that a model that isn't designed for forecasting shouldn't be used to forecast. But if it's not good for forecasting, it can't be good for e.g. policy changes either. In fact, without some really robust reasoning or empirical validation a model that can't be used to forecast can't be used for anything.

Now Britonomist is in good company as Olivier Blanchard has said almost the exact same thing he said in his blog post on five classes of macro models where Blanchard separated policy models from forecasting models. But I think that's evidence of some big fundamental issues in economic methodology. As I'm going to direct this post at a general audience, please don't take me being pedantic as talking down to Econ — on my own, I'd probably write this post entirely in terms of differential geometry on high dimensional manifolds (which is what the following argument really is).

The key assumption underlying the ability to forecast or determine the effects of policy changes is the ceteris paribus assumption. The basic idea is that the stuff you don't include is either negligible or cancels out on average. It's basically a more specific form of Hume's uniformity of nature. Let's think of the ceteris paribus condition as a constraint on the ocean underneath a boat. The boat is our macro model. You can think of the un-modeled variables as the curvature of the Earth (the variables that vary slowly) and the waves on the ocean (the variables that average out). [After comment from Britonomist on Twitter, I'd like to add that these are just examples. There can also be "currents" — i.e. things that aren't negligible — in the ceteris paribus condition. In physics, we'd consider these variables as ones that vary slowly (i.e. the current is roughly the same a little bit to the west or south), but people may take "vary slowly" to mean aren't very strong which is not what I mean here.]

Here's a picture:


The ceteris paribus condition lets us move the boat to the west and say that the sea is similar there so our boat still floats (our model still works). We only really know that our boat floats in an epsilon (ε) sized disk near where we started, so checking that it floats when we move west (i.e. comparison to data) is still important.

Now let's say east-west is time. Moving west with the boat is forecasting with the model. Moving north and south is changing policy. We move south, we change some collection of policy parameters in, say, the Taylor rule for a concrete example. The key takeaway here is that the ceteris paribus condition under the boat is the same for both directions we take the model: policy or forecasting.


It's true that the seas could get rougher to the south or a storm might be off in the distance to the northwest which may limit the distance we can travel in a particular direction under a given ceteris paribus scenario. But if we can't take our model to the west even a short distance, then we can't take our model to the south even a short distance. A model that can't forecast can't be used for policy [1]. This is because our ceteris paribus condition must coincide for both directions at the model origin. If it's good enough for policy variations, then it's good enough for temporal variations. Saying it's not good enough means knowing a lot about the omitted variables and their behavior [2].

And the truth is that looking at forecasts and policy changes are usually not orthogonal. You look at the effect of policy changes over a period of time. You're usually heading at least a little northwest or southwest instead of due south or due north.

But additionally there is the converse: if your model can't forecast, then it's probably useless for policy as well unless that manifold has the weird properties I describe in footnote [1]. Another way to put this is that saying a model can be used for policy changes but not forecasting implies an unnaturally large (or small) scale defined by the ratio of policy parameter changes to temporal changes [3]. Movement in time is somehow a much bigger step than movement in parameter space.

Now it is entirely possible this is actually the way things are! But there had better be really good reasons (such as really good agreement with the empirical data). Nice examples where this is true in physics are phase transitions. Sometimes a small change in parameters (or temperature) leads to a large qualitative change in model output (water freezes instead of getting colder). Effectively saying a macroeconomic model that can be used for policy but not forecasting is saying there's something like a phase transition for small perturbations of temperature.

This all falls under the heading of scope conditions. Until we collect empirical data from different parts of the ocean and see if our boat floats or sinks, we only really know about an "epsilon-sized ball" near the origin (per Noah Smith at the link). Empirical success gives us information about how big epsilon is. Or — if our theory is derived from a empirically successful framework — we can explicitly derive scope conditions (e.g. we can show using relativity that Newtonian physics is in scope for v << c). However, claims that a macro model is good for policy but not forecasting is essentially a nontrivial claim about model scope that needs to be much more rigorous than "it's POSSIBLE" (in reference to my earlier post on John Cochrane being unscientific), "it's not actually falsified", "it's just a toy model", or "it makes sense to this one economist".

And this is where both Blanchard and Britonomist are being unscientific. You can't really have a model that's good for policy but not forecasting without a lot of empirical validation. And since empirical validation is hard to come by in macro, there's no robust reason to say a model is good for one thing and not another. As Britonomist says, sometimes some logical argument is better than nothing in the face of uncertainty. People frequently find as much comfort in the pretense of knowledge as in actual knowledge. But while grasping at theories without empirical validation is sometimes helpful (lots of Star Trek episodes require Captain Picard to make decisions based on unconfirmed theories, for example), it is just an example of being decisive, not being scientific [4].

...

Footnotes

[1] This is where the differential geometry comes in handy. Saying a model can be used for policy changes (dp where p is the vector of parameters) but not for forecasting (dt where t is time) implies some pretty strange properties for the manifold the model defines (with its different parameters and at different times). In particular, it's "smooth" in one direction and not another.

Another way to think of this is that time is just another parameter as far as a mathematical model is concerned and we're really looking at variations dp' with p' = (p, t).

[2] Which can happen when you're working in a well-defined and empirically validated theoretical framework (and your model is some kind of expansion where you take only leading order terms in time changes but, say, up to second order terms in parameter changes). This implies you know the scale relating temporal and parameter changes I mention later in the post.

[3] |dp| = k dt with k >> 1. The scale is k and 1/k is some unnatural time scale that is extremely short for some reason. In this "unnatural" model, I can apparently e.g. double the marginal propensity to consume but not take a time step a quarter ahead.

[4] As a side note, the political pressure to be decisive runs counter to being scientific. Science deals with uncertainties by creating and testing multiple hypotheses (or simply accepting the uncertainty). Politics deals with uncertainty by choosing a particular action. That is a source of bad scientific methodology in economics where models are used to draw conclusions where the scientific response would be to claim "we don't know".

10 comments:

  1. hello, jason. I'm a fan of your work (math modelling and micro/macro issue mainly; also, I bought your book), and I can hear you loud and clear most of the times. I have just a few quibbles re the pretext of posts like these, namely the (to me) very opaque "policy implications" argument.

    I'm under the impression that, unless we're talking about some atmospheric allure of econ and "mainstream econ" (whatever filtered through the econ talk on the mediasphere), economic research has very few, almost zero, political implications (don't mean "political theory", we better not mistake the two things) beyond the pretty much trivial ones (eg: politicians should avoid stealing and be good guy and not sell themeselves to lobby interests ... or, that countries with high debts and poor econ performance need structural adjustments, & so on & forth)

    so: apart from said econ talk, I find it harder to venture some "policy" being inspired by economic theory, unless you mean that politics just interacts with the latter, if not instrumentally (ie: with the agency on the side of politics/interest groups). JMK's statement that politicians are prisoners of some dead economist is a self-celebrating prank of a relevant economist who, for personal and status reasons, happened to be very influential to politicians and many colleagues refreain it themselves to feel more significant.

    politics seeks power more than not and, in order to justify it, uses all that is available: from the values of the traditional heteronormative family to JMK, to "historical research", if useful. Of course they are just fig leaves, instrumental misuse of "science" and "research".

    I'm pretty much confident that 90% of scholars in the field of, say, Growth Theory - GT today as it is today - knows that GT is able to give very little political guidance. and whoever pretends the opposite knows to lie, basically.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. If you click the second link at the top of this post, you can find discussion and sources for two academic economists (one of whom is at Harvard and the author of the most popular introductory undergraduate Econ texts in the US, the other is at Stanford) making arguments in defense of the corporate tax cuts put forward by the Trump administration. They are both using the neoclassical growth model to do so.

      So there you have it: academic economists using growth theory to advocate policy.

      Delete
    2. yeah, I saw that - and I'm on your side. I'm pointing at a rather different focus, that is: are we entitled to regard this or that economic scholar (with his own amount of patently political sympathies/belief/desiderata) as a coryphaeus of the uhmm... scientific community? as in "What Economists Have To Tell You". you can rephrase it this way: "can he consider himself entitled to speak as______ of the scientific community?") IOW, is there something we can reasonably refer to as the Economic Consensus at all, holding any strong stance on what the policy prescriptions should be? y/n; I, for one, can think of a few economic theorists (or growth theory scholars) who are not on "the left" and yet strongly disagree with the tax cuts plan...so, I'm not sure the phenomenon we're dealing with on here counts as a matter of a "policy implication" problem stemming from what econ research has to positively say - however silly and unscientific those phenomena happen to be, whatever the next two economists positively say.

      Delete
    3. No one person really speaks for the scientific community just as I'd say that no one person speaks for the economic community.

      My discussion at the second link in the post above was really pointing out something that seems widespread using Cochrane and Mankiw (and DeLong, and Krugman) as an example. It's of course true that a single person isn't a good sample of the way economists think about problems, but I've actually written about this many times using many different examples. It's a kind of pervasive mode of thinking that isn't very scientific.

      As a side note, Cochrane himself says:

      "May economists falsely think of themselves as scientists who just “write up” research. We are not; we are primarily writers."

      https://faculty.chicagobooth.edu/john.cochrane/research/papers/phd_paper_writing.pdf

      So me calling Cochrane unscientific shouldn't really be very controversial since he says himself he's not very scientific.

      In a sense, I am arguing that economics (especially macroeconomics) needs to become more scientific**. Some of this has to do with the way they data, some has to do with the way they treat theory.

      **They could also become *less* scientific in a defensible way -- becoming more philosophical. But the sort of middle ground they've staked out is a kind of false scientism that only behaves scientifically when the results come out the way they like.

      Delete
    4. I cannot do other than fully agree, also I concur with you the second link speaks volumes about one of the disease in contemporaneous macro research (this stuff tends to dominate the debate, distort the search, conceal or make sense of results, and so on)

      and it's not controversial.

      but that's not a problem of the sample size - "cochrane, mankiw or lucas or romer,...,n"; it's that the policy implication issue as a conceptual framing for THIS derailment doesn't hold, imho.
      1. we can bellyache that there's a lack of science in econ research, whatever the reasons are, but (2.) the fact shit like that happens is mostly exogenous to the former; the latter (2.) being not a methodological, theorethical or not-getting-data-right problem, like 1. it's completely different argument.

      of course, if there was some hard economics out there, "2." would easely get silenced - but is it any useful to put it that way? while we still have no better econ... my impression is that, say, it would just legitimate a left vs right querrelle, which then again dosn't fall in the domain of 1.
      as regards the first post i wrote, what i said is that there is little "directly usable" that even frontier economic research can provide (something that yes, even cochrane seem to admit)

      Delete
  2. I like your explanation here Jason.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Last paragraph:

    "And since empirical validation is hard to come be in macro..."

    "be" should be "by"

    ReplyDelete
  4. How do you think Blanchard, Cochrane etc would answer if asked

    "How would you know if your model is wrong?"

    Isn't that a question all modelers should be responsible for having a good answer for? At the very least I would think they'd be interested in knowing themselves, perhaps turning to other experts to help them arrive at a method of testing it. So while they may not take on the responsibility themselves, they should at least acknowledge that there ought to be a way to test it and it should be tested, and that the tests should be good ones.

    I actually asked Cochrane that once a year or two ago about a model he was discussing, and to my surprise he responded. His response wasn't really an answer though, if I recall correctly.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. They would probably respond with some sort of non-answer, but then again it's hard for me to get inside economists' heads because the way they treat models is *so* foreign to me and my training in physics.

      Maybe I should ask Britonomist this question.

      Delete

Comments are welcome. Please see the Moderation and comment policy.

Also, try to avoid the use of dollar signs as they interfere with my setup of mathjax. I left it set up that way because I think this is funny for an economics blog. You can use € or £ instead.

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.