Sunday, April 3, 2016

Marvelous demonstration that this blog post is too narrow to contain


I'm not sure some of these critiques of economics are really pushing the ball forward. Here's Geoffrey Hodgson writing at Evonomics:
The problem is that utility maximization is unfalsifiable as an explanation of behavior. As I show more fully in my 2013 book entitled "From Pleasure Machines to Moral Communities", utility maximization can fit any real-world evidence, including behavior that appears to suggest preference inconsistency.
Emphasis in the original.

First, Hodgson doesn't show it here at all, so it's kind of a stretch to say it is shown "more fully" somewhere else. Even NYT articles about Fermat's last theorem give some indication as to how something was demonstrated. I don't want to have to buy Hodgson's book to figure out that he's wrong (largely because of the strength of the second and third points).

Second, preference inconsistency means that there is some set of inputs for which U(A) < U(B), and U(B) < U(C) but also U(C) < U(A) [corrected]. This means the utility function U(x) cannot be represented by a real function (since real numbers are a total order). Maximization is a mathematical process of finding the largest value of an objective function over a domain for which the range is a total order. Therefore finding preference inconsistency would be evidence against utility maximization [1]. This makes utility maximization falsifiable, regardless of whether we find preference inconsistency in the real world or not.

Third, utility maximization has already been "falsified" for individuals by many, many experiments (see e.g. here). However, just because it has been falsified does not mean it is not useful. Newtonian physics has been falsified by quantum mechanics and relativity; it's still used everyday.

Finally, is Hodgson tying to say there really isn't any preference inconsistency when he says "appears to suggest"? That's one way to square the circle, but a rather grandiose one. Is he saying every instance of preference inconsistency can be shown to be consistent using some other utility function? Preference inconsistency doesn't exist, therefore utility maximization is unfalsifiable? That might actually work. But it appears to violate some deep properties of numbers (i.e. the total order), so utility would have to be something besides a number. But that is the point -- the theory of utility is that utility is a number (or ordering), so finding that it is not a number is falsifying the theory.

In the end, the problem with utility maximization is that it is wrong ("falsified") about how people behave, not that it can't be shown to be wrong.

...

Footnotes:

[1] It may be possible that there exists an effective theory that has preference consistency made up of preference-inconsistent agents.

3 comments:

  1. Good catch. I'm puzzled as well.

    When Hodgson writes:

    The problem is that utility maximization is unfalsifiable as an explanation of behavior. As I show more fully in my 2013 book entitled "From Pleasure Machines to Moral Communities", utility maximization can fit any real-world evidence"

    It seems to me, he is referring to the definition of utility function:

    u: X->R such that x is strictly preferred to y if and only if u(x) > u(y)

    Clearly, that does not explain why x is strictly preferred to y, in the first place.

    Example. It's Sunday morning and the day is warm and sunny. Bob can either go to the beach (A) or to church (B). He strictly prefers A to B, therefore, one can say that u(A) > u(B). But why does he prefer A? We don't know. There are many alternative explanations: maybe he isn't much of a Christian, for instance.

    If his preferences were inverted, then u(B) > u(A). But, again, this is compatible with many explanations.

    However, I am not sure why this is a problem (if indeed this is what he is thinking about).

    ----------

    Nevertheless, like yourself, I do not understand what is it Hodgson means with the bit following that:

    including behavior that appears to suggest preference inconsistency.

    Maybe it was just a sloppy expression?

    Or maybe it was because Bob's preferences may change over time (he was born-again), or given different circumstances (it's a rainy, cold Sunday): Bob now strictly prefers church over beach. Before, it was the case that u(A) > u(B); now, we have u(B) > u(A).

    However, if this is the case, again I'm not sure why it should be a problem.



    B.L. Zebub

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. My attempt at briefly describing preference inconsistency in the post above is incorrect and I have to edit it. Preference inconsistency is not always about time-inconsistent preferences (although it could be), but about given a choice U(A) < U(B) and U(B) < U(C), but also chooses U(A) > U(C).

      Delete
    2. Lack of transitive property.

      B.L. Zebub

      Delete

Comments are welcome. Please see the Moderation and comment policy.

Also, try to avoid the use of dollar signs as they interfere with my setup of mathjax. I left it set up that way because I think this is funny for an economics blog. You can use € or £ instead.

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.